P ⇒ Q ⇔ ¬P ∨ Q
To me, this is one of most powerful manipulation rules that is extremely important to know so I didn't just want to memorize it. I wanted to understand it.
At first, It was kind of hard to wrap my head around the idea that "If P is true, then Q must be true" is the exact same as "P is not true or Q is true." When trying to connect these two statements using English only, it felt kind of hard to visualize, for me at least.
So I ended up working out several different ways to try to grasp this idea logically.
First, I did the truth tables:
P
|
Q
|
P ⇒ Q
|
¬P ∨ Q
|
T
|
T
|
T
|
T
|
T
|
F
|
F
|
F
|
F
|
T
|
T
|
T
|
F
|
F
|
T
|
T
|
After I did the truth tables, it was clearly evident that the implication and the logical disjunction statements were identical (according to the truth table). However, in terms of wording and a way of making English sense of it in my head, I was still not fully understanding this. So I continued:
Second, I did the Venn Diagram for both:
For P ⇒ Q : If P is true, then Q must be true, meaning there cannot be anything in the set of P where Q is not true, hence:
(Where P is the antecedent, Q is the consequent, and U is the universe. White is unoccupied)
For ¬P ∨ Q : Everything that is not P can be occupied and all of Q can be occupied, hence:
(Where P and Q are both predicates and U is the universe. White is unoccupied)
After creating the Venn Diagrams for both. It was starting to make a lot more sense. The Venn Diagrams are exactly the same. Since P implies Q means that "If P is true, then Q must be true" which means that there can't be any P's that aren't Q, then that would mean anything that's not P is fine. Also, if it's not P, then it doesn't matter what Q is for the implication as a whole to be true; vacuously. This is making a lot of sense. However, I still wanted to justify this some more!
Finally, I found negating the implication helped finalize my understanding of this manipulation rule:
First, "If P is true, then Q must be true" may be reworded with sets: "Every D that is also a P is also a Q" which would symbolically be:
∀x ∈ D, P(x) ⇒ Q(x)
So, if this was negated, the English would be "There exists a D that is also a P but is not Q." Symbolically:
∃x ∈ D, P(x) ∧ ¬Q(x)
So, I tried to negate the negation, to get back the original implication using De Morgan's Law:
¬(∃x ∈ D, P(x) ∧ ¬Q(x))
∀x ∈ D, ¬(P(x) ∧ ¬Q(x))
∀x ∈ D, (¬P ∨ Q)
Here I stopped and I didn't bother to change the disjunction back to an implication because I now saw that they are truly equivalent. This may have seemed like a roundabout way to get this the implication and disjunction stuck in your head, but this really helped me out! I thought to myself "I think I fully understand this concept now!"
It is great that you taking your time to understand the reasoning behind why the two are equivalent as opposed to just memorizing it!
ReplyDeleteGreat post, keep it up! :)
- Ekaterina
Thanks for taking the time to read this Kat!
Delete